Simplicity

From Nordan Symposia
(Redirected from Simplistic)
Jump to navigationJump to search

Lighterstill.jpg

Friend Qigongflower.jpg

Simplicity is being simple. It is a state, condition, or quality which things can be judged to have. It usually relates to the burden which a thing puts on someone trying to explain or understand it. Something which is easy to understand or explain is simple, in contrast to something complicated. In some uses, simplicity can be used to imply beauty, purity or clarity. Simplicity may also be used in a negative connotation to denote a deficit or insufficiency of nuance or complexity of a thing, relative to what is supposed to be required.

For lessons on the topic of Simplicity, follow this link.


The concept of simplicity has been related to truth in the field of epistemology. According to Occam's razor, all other things being equal, the simplest theory is the most likely to be true. In the context of human lifestyle, simplicity can denote freedom from hardship, effort or confusion. Specifically, it can refer to a simple living lifestyle.

Simplicity is a theme in the Christian religion. According to St. Thomas Aquinas, God is infinitely simple. The Roman Catholic and Anglican religious orders of Franciscans also strive after simplicity. Members of the Religious Society of Friends (Quakers) practice the Testimony of Simplicity, which is the simplifying of one's life in order to focus on things that are most important and disregard or avoid things that are least important.

In Philosophy & Science

The definition provided by Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy is that "Other things being equal simpler theories are better." There is a widespread philosophical presumption that simplicity is a theoretical virtue. This presumption that simpler theories are preferable appears in many guises. Often it remains implicit; sometimes it is invoked as a primitive, self-evident proposition; other times it is elevated to the status of a ‘Principle’ and labeled as such (for example, the ‘Principle of Parsimony’). However, it is perhaps best known by the name ‘Occam's (or Ockham's) Razor.’ Simplicity principles have been proposed in various forms by theologians, philosophers, and scientists, from ancient through medieval to modern times. Thus Aristotle writes in his Posterior Analytics,

We may assume the superiority ceteris paribus of the demonstration which derives from fewer postulates or hypotheses. [Aristotle, Posterior Analytics, transl. McKeon, [1963, p. 150].]

Moving to the medieval period, Aquinas writes

If a thing can be done adequately by means of one, it is superfluous to do it by means of several; for we observe that nature does not employ two instruments where one suffices (Aquinas 1945, p. 129).


Kant—in the Critique of Pure Reason—supports the maxim that "rudiments or principles must not be unnecessarily multiplied (entia praeter necessitatem non esse multiplicanda)" and argues that this is a regulative idea of pure reason which underlies scientists' theorizing about nature (Kant 1950, pp. 538–9). Both Galileo and Newton accepted versions of Occam's Razor. Indeed Newton includes a principle of parsimony as one of his three ‘Rules of Reasoning in Philosophy’ at the beginning of Book III of Principia Mathematica.

Rule I: We are to admit no more causes of natural things than such as are both true and sufficient to explain their appearances.

Newton goes on to remark that "Nature is pleased with simplicity, and affects not the pomp of superfluous causes" (Newton 1972, p. 398). Galileo, in the course of making a detailed comparison of the Ptolemaic and Copernican models of the solar system, maintains that "Nature does not multiply things unnecessarily; that she makes use of the easiest and simplest means for producing her effects; that she does nothing in vain, and the like" (Galileo 1962, p. 397). Nor are scientific advocates of simplicity principles restricted to the ranks of physicists and astronomers. Here is the chemist Lavoisier writing in the late 18th Century:

If all of chemistry can be explained in a satisfactory manner without the help of phlogiston, that is enough to render it infinitely likely that the principle does not exist, that it is a hypothetical substance, a gratuitous supposition. It is, after all, a principle of logic not to multiply entities unnecessarily (Lavoisier 1862, pp. 623–4).

Compare this to the following passage from Einstein, writing 150 years later.

The grand aim of all science…is to cover the greatest possible number of empirical facts by logical deductions from the smallest possible number of hypotheses or axioms (Einstein, quoted in Nash 1963, p. 173).

Quotes

  • "Things should be made as simple as possible, but no simpler."—Albert Einstein (1879–1955)
  • "You can always recognize truth by its beauty and simplicity."—Richard Feynman (1918–1988)
  • "Our lives are frittered away by detail; simplify, simplify."—Henry David Thoreau (1817–1862)
  • "Simplicity is the ultimate sophistication."—Leonardo da Vinci (1452–1519)[citation needed]
  • "If you can't describe it simply, you can't use it simply."—Anon
  • "Simplicity means the achievement of maximum effect with minimum means."—Koichi Kawana, architect of botanical gardens
  • "Perfection is achieved, not when there is nothing more to add, but when there is nothing left to take away."—Antoine de Saint Exupéry
"Simplicity is the direct result of profound thought."—Anon

Definitions

  • I. 1. Free from duplicity, dissimulation, or guile; innocent and harmless; undesigning, honest, open, straightforward.
2. Free from, devoid of, pride, ostentation, or display; humble, unpretentious.
3. a. Free from elaboration or artificiality; artless, unaffected; plain, unadorned. Usually implying that the simplicity is a merit, but sometimes (as in quot. 1827) with suggestion of sense 7.
b. Of persons: Free from over-refinement, unsophisticated, unspoiled.
  • II. 4. a. Of persons, or their origin: Poor or humble in condition; of low rank or position; undistinguished, mean, common.
b. In modest or apologetic use.
c. In phr. as simple as, or simple though, I stand here. Obs.
5. With designations or titles: Ordinary; not further distinguished in office or rank.
6. a. Of persons or their attire: Not marked by any elegance or grandeur; very plain or homely.
b. Similarly of living, diet, abode, etc. the simple life, a mode of life in which anything of the nature of luxury is intentionally avoided; also attrib. Hence simple-lifer, a follower or proponent of the simple life. Also simple-liver; simple-living vbl. n. and ppl. adj.
c. Ordinary, not festival. Obs.1
7. a. Small, insignificant, slight; of little account or value; also, weak or feeble.
b. Of price or sale: Low, poor. Obs.
8. Poor, wretched, pitiful, dismal. Obs.
9. Deficient in knowledge or learning; characterized by a certain lack of acuteness or quick apprehension:  ::a. Of persons (and animals).
b. Of mental powers, etc.
c. Of compositions, etc., esp. in apologetic use.
10. a. Lacking in ordinary sense or intelligence; more or less foolish, silly, or stupid; also, mentally deficient, half-witted (now dial.).
b. Simple Simon. ‘Simple Simon’ is the subject of various nursery rhymes, which may have given rise to the general use.
c. In bird-names, as simple tern (or viralve), warbler.
  • III. 11. a. With nothing added; considered or taken by itself; mere, pure, bare; single.
b. In phr. pure and simple. Cf. PURE a. 3.
12. a. Med. Of wounds, diseases, etc.: Unaccompanied by complications.
b. Law. Unattended by any strengthening circumstance; not specially confirmed. simple contract, one made by word of mouth or not under seal; also attrib.
13. Consisting or composed of one substance, ingredient, or element; uncompounded, unmixed (or nearly so): a. Of bodies or substances, esp. natural or organic.
b. Of medical or other preparations. simple colours
c. In general use.
14. a. Not composite or complex in respect of parts or structure.
b. spec. in scientific use.
c. Math. (a) Applied to a group that has no proper normal subgroup; and hence to an algebra or ring that has no proper ideal.
d. simple structure (Statistics): a model in which numerous variables, showing various degrees of correlation, have their variances assigned to a smaller number of factors in such a way that no factor affects all of the variables.
15. a. Not complicated or involved; presenting little or no complexity or difficulty.

References

  • Craig, E. Ed. (1998) Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. London, Routledge. simplicity (in Scientific Theory) p.780–783
  • Dancy, J. and Ernest Sosa, Ed.(1999) A Companion to Epistemology. Malden, Massachusetts, Blackwell Publishers Inc. simplicity p. 477–479.
  • Dowe, D. L., S. Gardner & G. Oppy (2007), "Bayes not Bust! Why Simplicity is no Problem for Bayesians", Brit. J. Phil. Sci., Vol. 58, Dec. 2007, 46pp. [Among other things, this paper compares MML with AIC.]
  • Edwards, P., Ed. (1967). The Encyclopedia of Philosophy. New York, The Macmillan Company. simplicity p.445–448.
  • Kim, J. a. E. S., Ed.(2000). A Companion to Metaphysics. Oxford, Blackwell Publishers. simplicity, parsimony p.461–462.
  • Maeda, J., (2006) Laws of Simplicity, MIT Press
  • Newton-Smith, W. H., Ed. (2001). A Companion to the Philosophy of Science. Malden, Massachusetts, Blackwell Publishers Ltd. simplicity p.433–441.
  • Sarkar, S. Ed. (2002). The Philosophy of Science—An Encyclopedia. London, Routledge. simplicity
  • Wilson, R. A. a. K., Frank C., (1999). The MIT Encyclopedia of the Cognitive Sciences. Cambridge, Massachusetts, The MIT Press. parsimony and simplicity p.627–629.

External links